Open access peer-reviewed chapter - ONLINE FIRST

Perspective Chapter: The Primacy of Freedom over Equality as a Condition for Peace from Jean-Jacques Rousseau to Pope John Paul II

Written By

Zdzisław Kieliszek

Submitted: 11 December 2023 Reviewed: 13 December 2023 Published: 22 March 2024

DOI: 10.5772/intechopen.1004176

New Perspectives on Global Peace IntechOpen
New Perspectives on Global Peace Edited by James P. Welch

From the Edited Volume

New Perspectives on Global Peace [Working Title]

Dr. James P. Welch

Chapter metrics overview

9 Chapter Downloads

View Full Metrics

Abstract

The author answers the question of which of the two values - freedom or equality – is more fundamental to peace in human relations. Four projects of public order are analyzed. First, J.J. Rousseau’s postulate that the fundamental condition for a peacefully functioning society is to guarantee equality among its members is discussed. Then, Karl Raimund Popper’s opposing idea that the fundamental principle of peaceful public life is the protection of freedom is presented. Then, A. de Tocqueville’s idea that religion plays a key role in a peaceful society, since its presence in the public sphere guarantees effective protection of citizens’ freedom and serves peace, is evoked. It also analyzes John Paul II’s observation that the Christian vision of man is in harmony with the ethos of a peaceful society whose fundamental value is freedom. It turns out that freedom is a more fundamental value than equality for peaceful relations between people. Moreover, the effectiveness of the defense of human freedom and the building of peace depends directly on the active presence of Christians in the public square. This activity should be manifested in the implementation of various educational and social projects by Christians.

Keywords

  • freedom
  • equality
  • J.J. Rousseau
  • A. de Tocqueville
  • K.R. Popper
  • John Paul II
  • peace

1. Introduction

Article One of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted in Paris on December 10, 1948, at the Third Session of the General Assembly of the United Nations, reads as follows: “All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights.”1The Declaration was intended by its authors to impose moral and political obligations on individual states, to induce them to comply with its provisions and to provide a lasting basis for international peace. Thus, the first article of the Declaration establishes the main moral-political criterion by which public orders should be judged, including in terms of their potential to promote or threaten international peace. The point is that, according to the Declaration’s authors, any state order that protects the freedom of its citizens and ensures their equality is peacefully creative. By contrast, state regimes that do not provide these guarantees should be considered a serious threat to world peace, and action should be taken to change them accordingly.

It is interesting to note that freedom is listed first, before equality, in the aforementioned article. One could conclude that the authors of the Declaration considered freedom to be the most important value for human beings, certainly more important than equality. This means, then, that, from the perspective of concern for world peace, these social regimes should be fostered and developed that do not so much provide people with equality, guaranteeing the protection of freedom.

In these reflections, an attempt will be made to support that the conviction of the authors of the Declaration to place freedom before equality is as correct as possible. This research will further attempt to clearly define what and why a concretely defined vision of humanity requires the true protection of human freedom and, therefore, the pursuit of peace. Four outstanding thinkers have been chosen as intellectual guides in this research: Jean-Jaques Rousseau, Karl Raimund Popper, Alexis Clérel, comte de Tocqueville, and John Paul II. They have not been randomly (nonchronologically) listed in this order by chance. Their thinking appears to be complementary. Issues not taken up by the first author are subsequently taken up (or addressed) by others. Therefore, it is not difficult to understand that the concept of public order, formulated by John Paul II, can be considered the most appropriate development of a project whose moral-political foundation is Article One of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.

Advertisement

2. J.J. Rousseau: equality as a condition for peace

J.J. Rousseau, in his seminal, political, and social work, on The Social Contract, states “Man is born free; and everywhere he is in chains. One thinks himself the master of others, and still remains a greater slave than they. How did this change come about? I do not know. What can make it legitimate? That question I think I can answer.”2

The above statement indicates the problem that Rousseau intends to solve. He will not concern himself with the actual process of the formation of societies. Rousseau will limit himself to the search for the principles on which any unjust social order is based. In this way, Rousseau will identify the main sources of social unrest. Injustice is to be understood here as any form of social bondage, and its existence presents a constant danger for the outbreak of struggles between people seeking freedom. The Social Contract is therefore a philosophical and juridical work, not a historical one. Rousseau considers the theses it contains to be normative, not hypothetical.3 This means, on the one hand, that according to its author, The Social Contract clearly identifies the source of social injustice and, on the other hand, defines the principles upon which a just and thus peace-promoting social system should be based.

Central to Rousseau’s entire conception is the assertion that the source of social injustice, and the real threat of the outbreak of unrest, lies in the political organization of society, not in the ontic human condition. The problem to be solved in creating a social order conducive to peaceful relations among human beings is to design political institutions that respect the freedom inherent in human beings.

According to Rousseau, the greatest threat to human freedom, and thus to social peace, is inequality among human beings. The main source of inequality is private property. It is also the fundamental source of strife among men.4 This follows from the fact that the principle of relating people to each other is to compare them to each other. Also, as the primary object of comparison among men is wealth, it differentiates them among themselves, making relations among individuals unequal and hostile for it is natural in every society that some people own more and others have less private property.5

However, the criticism of private property should not be understood as Rousseau advocating the introduction of collective property in society or even a communist type of property. Rousseau seems to have in mind the general idea of the development of any society. This development goes from a complete community to more and more individualized forms. In a complete community, all its members are completely equal. In individualized forms, individuals are increasingly different from each other. Therefore, the most important implication of this critique is that it is necessary to design political institutions that treat all citizens with absolute equality. Only in this way will it be possible to ensure both the natural freedom of each individual and peaceful relations between people.6

The desired political institutions, according to Rousseau, must be based on the collective will of all citizens and the social contract. By the former, the French thinker intends the common position of the people living in a given society with regard to all the problems and difficulties it faces;7 by the latter, he means the simultaneous abandonment by all individuals of the pursuit of their personal goals and the absolute submission of all decisions to the collective will and the political body that embodies it.8 Only such a social order remains in harmony with the natural (ideal) state of human life and guarantees peaceful relations between people. In this state, no individual exists as a separate element of the community but remains in full and friendly communion with other men, and all men remain equal to each other and enjoy real, not imaginary, freedom.9 The former consists in doing what is consistent with reason; the latter appears to be mere arbitrariness.10 According to Rousseau, thanks to the conclusion of a social contract with other people, and the submission of all citizens to the collective will, equal rights, true freedom, and social peace are guaranteed to each individual.11

Rousseau places the political body that embodies the collective will, as the guardian of equality, freedom, and peace. Only this political body, according to the French philosopher, is entitled to protect them. In extreme cases, this protection can even adopt the form of coercion. This applies to citizens who do not submit to the collective will and thus violate the previously concluded agreement. According to Rousseau, such an attitude is tantamount to questioning the equality of all citizens, a rejection of true freedom, and a lack of peaceful attitude toward other people. In such a case, the political body is entitled to apply coercion to certain citizens. This is about the right to force citizens to respect each other’s equality and to remain in peaceful relations with each other.12

Based on the social views of Rousseau, outlined above, it can be noted that the conception of social life in which the active subject is not an individual but the whole community becomes clear. Consequently, this means that the French thinker – as if contrary to his intentions – actually deprives man of his freedom. During the French Revolution and the history of the socialist movement, the flaws in Rousseau’s concepts became apparent. As is well known, in the first case, the decisions of the collective will of the people were treated as a justification for terror, which, after all, should be considered the most radical possible violation of human freedom and the extreme deprivation of peaceful relations between people; while in the second case, the idea of the dictatorship of the proletariat also stands in clear contradiction to human freedom and the desire for peaceful regulation of relations between people. I am far from blaming Rousseau for the horrors of the French Revolution or the consequences of the dictatorship of the proletariat. However, it is difficult not to see that, in both cases, what is somehow hidden in the French philosopher’s conception is very clearly revealed: the absolute power of a political body to decide the actual fate of certain people or certain communities, including the complete deprivation of their freedom or even their existence due to the violation of the broadly understood interests of a certain community.13

Rousseau’s social vision should therefore be described as a totalitarian project in which there is absolutely no room for any opposition to the will of the whole (in political practice, this should be understood as the will of the majority) of the citizens and the specific political body that embodies it. In a society built according to the recommendations of the French author, there is also no place for arbitrary decisions made by individuals or human communities smaller than a larger-than-life community of which they are a part, which amounts to questioning human autonomy (freedom) and individuality and threatens to cause outbreaks of social unrest.14

Where is the error that led Rousseau, contrary to his original intentions, to design a social order in which there is ultimately no place for either human freedom or peaceful human relations? When we speak of the mistakes made by the French thinker, we usually refer to his erroneous assumption that the source of injustice and social unrest is the institutional organization of public life or the perception of man as an inherently good being, i.e., incapable of harming others. It must be admitted that these are indeed mistaken assumptions, which are not without influence on this or that formulation of Rousseau’s concept.15 It appears however, that he also made a mistake that is not clear: on the level of institutional arrangements, he puts equality before freedom. The point is that Rousseau seems to have put forward the following thesis: the only effective means of protecting the freedom of citizens and ensuring peaceful relations between people is to guarantee them an equal influence on the shaping of the public order in which they live. In fact, the French thinker noted that as the greatest threat to freedom and peace is inequality between people, guaranteeing freedom and peace to citizens requires that people first be equal. Meanwhile, I think that, by equating citizens with each other, an even greater threat to their freedom and peace is created. Rousseau did not seem to realize this when he developed the concept of public order.

Advertisement

3. Karl Raimund Popper: freedom as the basis of social peace

To understand why equality should not take precedence over freedom, it is worth considering the thought of the Austrian philosopher Karl R. Popper. In his intellectual autobiography, Unended Quest, he says “For nothing could be better than living a modest, simple, and free life in an egalitarian society. It took some time before I recognized this as no more than a beautiful dream; that freedom is more important than equality; that the attempt to realize equality endangers freedom; and that, if freedom is lost, there will not even be equality among the unfree.”16

Karl Raimund Popper’s thought is part of the currentpolitical and social reflection that emerged in Western Europe and the United States after the Second World War. Thinkers belonging to this current (besides Popper, the most important are F.A. von Hayek and I. Berlin) attempt to show the true roots of totalitarianism and sketch models of a social order in which human freedom is the highest value.17

The main issue that Popper deals with in his most important work on socio-political problems, The Open Society and Its Enemies, is the question of the proper organization of public order. A properly organized society is what Popper calls an “open society.” By “open society,” the Austrian philosopher means a social system in which the individual has the right to make completely free decisions about his or her life, all citizens have equal opportunities for social advancement, and the organization of public institutions promotes competition among citizens. Competition should not be understood as a hostile rivalry. Popper has in mind a kind of competition between people for worthy goals, with the complete exclusion of the use of force or violence. The tool of human interaction in such an understanding of competition is not persuasion or appeal, but argumentation and rational justification of the validity of one’s views. An “open society” therefore allows a diversity of views among its citizens. The principle of internal development and improvement of existing political and social institutions in the “open society” is the cooperation of citizens, exchange of opinions of citizens on specific issues, and joint search for optimal solutions to given problems. Approaching the truth in terms of social life consists, in turn, of 1) rejecting solutions that do not work at a given moment and do not seem to correspond to the objective state of affairs; 2) designing and implementing innovative ideas in their place; 3) citizens jointly evaluating new solutions and rejecting those that are unacceptable at a given moment and must be replaced by new designs (in this way, the entire process begins to repeat itself).18

The opposite and, in a sense, the only alternative to the “open society,” according to Popper, is the “closed society.”19 It is characterized by the restriction of the freedom of citizens, the curatorship of the state over them, the omnipresence of legal regulations restricting the freedom of action of citizens, censorship, the insistence on the adoption by all citizens of a single worldview doctrine considered true by the authorities, the tendency toward a totalitarian form of government. According to the Austrian thinker, examples of “closed society” projects are primarily the political and social concepts of Plato, G.W.F. Hegel, and Karl Marx. In these projects, there is a conviction of the possibility of realizing a single, desirable model of political-social order. The political institutions within such an order uphold a single moral doctrine that is considered binding.20

Although Karl Raimund Popper does not explicitly mention Rousseau’s concept as an example of a “closed society,” it seems that it too can be considered a typical model of a “closed society.”21 This is because it reveals very clearly the main characteristics of this type of society: the lack of respect for individual freedom and the pernicious tendency to build an ideological (totalitarian) society, guided by a single worldview that is considered the most appropriate.22

All projects of the “closed society” seek to realize the vision of holistic good. According to their authors, it can be achieved only through the realization of a certain model of social order, which appears to be ideal.23 According to Popper, such a thesis is based on the mistaken belief that socio-historical reality is determined by “iron laws of destiny” that can be known and according to which the social order should be shaped.24 The belief that such laws exist is mistaken because the future appears to be open-ended.25 Thus, there are no laws that determine (i.e., somehow summarily conclude) human history.26

According to Popper, the openness of history is indicated by the observation that the course of human history depends primarily on the development of science and the future states of consciousness of individual human beings. Neither, in turn, can be reasonably predicted. Therefore, the future development of human history cannot be accurately determined. This means that the future is completely open, i.e., it is a matter of many different coincidences, accidents, and more or less rationally justified decisions of certain people, and in the long run, nothing can be precisely determined. Therefore, it is not possible to predict future human ideas rationally and unambiguously about what a good human society should look like in the future and what specific solutions to specific problems should look like.27

As the history of humankind is open-ended, it is not possible to determine the future history with precision. This means that the future of humankind is unpredictable. Consequently, it is not possible to determine how to build a social order in which peace would prevail permanently. According to the Austrian thinker, the “skeleton” of a peaceful social order is determined by the idea of an “open society” rather than a “closed society.” Thus, the peaceful search for ever-better solutions to specific social problems is possible only in an “open society.” In addition, an “open society” is conducive to peacefully meeting the needs of a given community, which are constantly changing over time. In contrast, this is impossible in the case of a “closed society.” All orders built according to the idea of a “closed society” attempt to realize a preconceived, specific vision of an ideal public order. In this way, citizens are deprived of the opportunity to gradually improve and develop specific solutions to a specific situation.28

The “open society,” despite its undoubted advantages over the “closed society,” is not, however, without its shortcomings.29 According to Popper, the most important of these appears to be the possibility of being subject to various kinds of moral-political imperfections. This should be understood in such a way that the specific institutional solutions adopted within the framework of the “open society” are to some extent a result of the moral-intellectual level of the society as a whole and, in particular, of the specific individuals who hold political power at a given time. Thus, the higher this level, the greater the guarantee of a more peaceful functioning of a given society. Of course, the opposite is also true – the lower this level, the more vulnerable a given society is to the outbreak of social unrest. The disadvantage of the “open society” understood in this way is structural as it is directly inscribed in the functioning of the whole system and cannot be avoided. This does not mean, however, that the “open society” should be rejected for this reason and considered an inappropriate model of social order that best serves the cause of peace.30 According to the Austrian philosopher, the postulate that follows from the recognition of this flaw is quite different: “What we need and what we want is to moralize politics, and not to politicize morals.”31

Returning here to the concept of Rousseau, it can be noted that, in his case – from the point of view of Popper’s thought – we are dealing with the politicization of morality. The French philosopher sketches a vision of public order that has the task of realizing a particular moral idea, misunderstood as the general good. It is the belief in the primacy of the equality of all human beings over their right to decide freely about their lives.

It is difficult to disagree with Popper’s justification of the primacy of freedom over equality and the related idea of the superiority of the “open society” over the “closed society.” The Austrian thinker also rightly points out that the former should not be regarded as a completely finished construction. Rather, “open society” is only a guideline for building a social order that serves the cause of peace in order to protect human freedom. Popper’s postulate for the moralization of politics also seems to be correct. Paradoxically, however, the greatest weakness of the idea of the “open society” lies in such a postulate. By placing human freedom above all other values, Popper deprived the concrete human being of any guidance as to how morally decent he is to realize his goals and on what concrete moral principles the public life of the “open society” is to be based. In other words, while the Austrian philosopher made the all-too-common postulate of “moralizing politics,” he failed to show on what moral values the “open society” should be based. Thus, Popper’s idea is, in sum, an attempt to outline a morally neutral space of social life in which adherents of different world views would find their place. But the existence of such a morally neutral space is impossible. It is necessary to identify very precisely the specific moral values on which the “open society” must be based.32

Advertisement

4. Alexis Clérel, comte de Tocqueville: the religious foundation of peaceful liberty

To find their previously articulated values, it is worth referring to the reflections of de Tocqueville. This French philosopher, who lived a century before Popper, proposed a solution that, on the one hand, is in harmony with the idea of an “open society” and, on the other hand, points out that the protection of human freedom, oriented toward the peaceful coexistence of people, requires the presence of strictly defined values in the public sphere.33

In his major work, Democracy in America, de Tocqueville analyses the mechanisms of the American public order of the time, which seems to him to be a perfect example of a democratic system. The French philosopher notes that it is noticeable what kind of social system disappears with the advent of democracy. This system is broadly defined as the aristocratic rule. What is less clear, however, is what democracy can bring in the future. Therefore, it is necessary to analyze what can be expected from democracy, i.e., what opportunities it offer humanity and what dangers it generate.34

The author of Democracy in America notes that democracy is not so much a fully formed and ready-made system as a public order, which can take on different institutional expressions, depending on the historical, geographical, economic, political, or cultural conditions of the society that creates it. The fundamental values of this order are freedom and equality, the former being the more fundamental. The point is that without freedom there can be no democracy. While equality is also a formal condition for the existence of democracy, it is somehow secondary to freedom. When de Tocqueville speaks of the subordination of equality to freedom, he has in mind equality of opportunity, not the actual equality of citizens (equality in this case would mean a certain equality). Freedom is more fundamental to the democratic system. The reason being, that in democracy, citizens are always free to realize the possibilities available to them in the current situation. In other words, democracy is a public order in which citizens are completely free to decide how to realize opportunities before them. The freedom to choose how to realize opportunities here applies both to citizens taken as specific individuals and to citizens grouped in smaller or larger groups that make up the community as a whole.35 Because the freedom of citizens is understood in this way, the democratic order can take on different institutional expressions in the case of a given society. This expression depends directly on the choices made by its members at any given time.

According to de Tocqueville, the direct dependence of the institutional form of a given democratic order on the actual choices made by its citizens is, paradoxically, the greatest weakness of democracy. Although nothing is imposed on the citizens and they themselves freely make certain choices, which is a great advantage of democracy (understood here in the spirit of Popper’s idea of an “open society”), at the same time, the actual choices made by the citizens can be de-structural for the entire system. Understood in this way, the weakness of the democratic order is a consequence of the internal tensions and contradictions inherent within it. It is therefore necessary to understand the mechanisms that govern it.36

The French thinker notes that the democratic way, in which public order functions, is primarily conducive to the spread of false attitudes in society. These are mediocrity, intellectual and spiritual mediocrity, selfishness, passivity, and involuntary submission to the majority of individual citizens. The spread of such attitudes results – first – from the fact that people value equality more than freedom.37 This is because the benefits of bringing equality to society are felt almost immediately, while the harms only become apparent over time. In the case of freedom, the opposite is somewhat true. The freedom given to citizens to make certain choices creates some anxiety and uncertainty about the rightness of those choices and creates space for citizens to compete quite freely with each other. The benefits, (including the prospect of unfettered personal intellectual and spiritual development) of such a way of operating public order, are gradually and very slowly revealed, while the harms (including this fear and uncertainty) are felt almost immediately.38 Second, the mechanisms of the democratic order lead to a gradual atomization of society. This also leads to an increase in the anonymity of citizens, as the ties that bind them become weaker. These bonds are weakened by the pluralism of values, attitudes, and beliefs among which citizens are completely free to choose.39 Third, the way democracy works means that the desire for material well-being, which is inherent in human nature and is not fundamentally a bad thing, slowly turns citizens away from big ideas and makes them more and more concerned only with temporal matters. Thus, instead of spending their time in intellectually and spiritually creative ways, citizens pay more and more attention to visible, immediate, and calculable goals.40 Also, fourth, the principles of democracy imply that the majority of citizens, who make up the broad public opinion, exert an ever-increasing pressure on the individual. This pressure forms in the individual citizen the conviction that the truth is always on the side of the majority. In this way, public opinion, formed by the majority of citizens, provides the individual with ready-made models of attitudes and beliefs, relieving him of the trouble of taking an independent stand on certain problems.41

According to de Tocqueville, the mechanisms of the democratic order described above can lead to its total destruction. Therefore, it must be somehow protected from this danger.42 The French philosopher notes that there are certain institutional arrangements inherent in the democratic order that protect it from self-destruction. Among the most important of these are freedom of the press, freedom of custom, freedom of association, the principle of civil disobedience, the right of citizens to take an active part in public life, or the grounding of law in the prevailing morality of a given society. These solutions seem necessary, but they are not sufficient. For there is still the danger of an inappropriate formation of the ethos of a given society, the outbreak of social unrest, and the spread of attitudes dangerous to the democratic order.43

According to de Tocqueville, religion plays a key role in saving democracy from self-destruction.44 Only it guarantees the ethos of a given society at an appropriate level. The French thinker does not have a specific form of religion in mind here, but any form of religion, that is, the belief in the existence of a widely understood entity transcending temporal reality. Religion understood in this way protects against violations by citizens of key moral principles that are fundamental to the proper functioning of democracy. These include honesty in relations with other people, respect for them, a peaceful attitude toward people, opposition to selfish attitudes, an awareness of certain obligations to other people, and an appropriate distance from the pursuit of worldly happiness.45

De Tocqueville’s observations on the dangers of the democratic functioning of the public order are very pertinent. In fact, two opposing tendencies are structurally inscribed in this order: the anarchization of society and the totalization of public space by a single dominant vision of reality. Both threaten the destruction of the system.46 Similarly, the French thinker rightly points out that stopping these destructive tendencies is made possible only by an adequate moral level of society. This means that strictly defined values and beliefs must be present in the ethos of a given community.47

If we place de Tocqueville’s analyses against the background of the thoughts of the two philosophers mentioned earlier (Rousseau and. Popper), we can say that they appear much profound, more penetrating and, above all, more accurate. De Tocqueville, analyzing the mechanisms of democracy, precisely pointed out the dangers for democracy itself, which Rousseau obviously failed to notice. First, there is the occupation of the public space by a single vision of reality that is considered correct and desirable by the majority. On the other hand, in contrast to the Austrian thinker, de Tocqueville rightly underscored that if democracy (“open society”) is to function well, including serving to build peaceful relations between people, and if we want to save it at all, social space cannot be morally neutral. Leaving this space empty risks destroying democracy itself, something Popper failed to recognize.

The author of Democracy in America also rightly observed that religion plays a key role in the formation of an ethos of democratic order that serves peace. But can we agree with the French philosopher that all forms of faith play an equal role? In other words, is each form of religion equally capable of creating and sustaining in a democratic society the appropriate ethos necessary for the duration and proper functioning of a public order that protects human freedom and serves the cause of peace? To answer these questions, it is worth referring to the social reflection of John Paul II.

Advertisement

5. John Paul II: the Christian vision of man in the service of Freedom and Peace

John Paul II dedicated three social encyclicals to the organization of public order: Laborem Exercens, Sollicitudo Rei Socialis, and Centesimus Annus. The first of these documents discusses issues related to human work; the second discusses problems related to the economic, political, and cultural development of human societies; the third presents a vision of a peacefully organized social order based on two foundations: freedom and justice. In all three encyclicals, the Pope refers to the Church’s past tradition and tries to re-read it in the light of the current social situation. In the case of what is of particular interest here: John Paul II severely criticizes the organization and mechanisms of the peaceful functioning of the democratic social order. This is because he points out its weaknesses and, at the same time, proposes appropriate steps to be taken to save it in the first place and then to allow its further peaceful development.48

According to John Paul II, a profound reflection on the question of human work is the key to understanding all questions related to the problem of the peaceful organization of social life.49 The reflection shows that “work is a fundamental dimension of humankind’s existence on earth.”50 This means that, through work, people become more human and develop self-realization in the world.51 The human being thus appears as the sole subject and direct cause of working.52 This last observation is of great significance. It indicates that the criterion for identifying a peacefully organized social order is the treatment of the individual human being by public authorities. In any social order aimed at building peaceful human relations, people must be treated as real subjects of social life, capable of their own free initiative. If, on the other hand, an individual is treated as a small cog in a large mechanism, moved from top to down by some political body, then a given social order will not serve the cause of peace.53 In other words, in a peacefully organized society, the freedom to which each person is entitled is protected first and foremost, and in a society in which human freedom is constantly threatened, the outbreak of unrest is inevitable.54

John Paul II, by putting the matter in this way, as presented above, seems on the one hand to support Popper’s project of the “open society” and on the other hand to indicate that the path proposed by Rousseau is completely wrong. In the first case, the individual person is seen as the subject of public life, while, in the second case, this subject is society, and in particular a particular political body representing it. It would seem, therefore, that by making the individual person the subject of social life, the Pope is acknowledging the crucial place of freedom and its priority over equality in the vision of a peacefully organized public system, of which he considers democracy to be a good model for today.55

By making man the subject of social life, John Paul II also seems to invite representatives of different ideological traditions to work together toward the achievement of a common goal. This is to work for the good of the concrete person and for the peaceful organization of human relations. According to the Pope, only if a broad consensus is formed among all the groups that make up a given community around this goal can they succeed in building a peacefully functioning public order.56 In this way, the reflection of John Paul II seems very close to the reflections of de Tocqueville. Both underscore that the public sphere in a peacefully functioning democracy cannot be morally empty but must have a well-defined content. It is shaped above all by obligations such as honesty toward others, respect for their inherent human dignity, openness to those in need (especially the weak and the poor), or an appropriate distance from material goods.57

According to John Paul II, if this space remains morally empty or is filled with inappropriate content, the peaceful functioning of democracy will be constantly threatened.58 This follows from the fact that the mechanisms of functioning of democracy alone59 will gradually lead to increasing spiritual underdevelopment of society.60 This means that it is impossible to build a peacefully functioning social order unless it is based on a properly ordered and well-defined hierarchy of goods and values.61 According to the Pope, the key role in the formation of this hierarchy in the consciousness of society is played by religion,62” and in particular by Christianity.63

In this way, John Paul II added the reflections of de Tocqueville. The French thinker posited that every form of religion serves equally to maintain the ethos necessary for the peaceful functioning of the democratic order in society. Rousseau did not, however, privilege Christianity in this regard. The Pope, on the other hand, while not denying the importance of various forms of religion, clearly indicates that the Christian vision of reality coincides with the moral ideas underlying the order which guarantees human freedom and serves the cause of peace.64

As repeatedly emphasized, throughout this chapter, the ideological foundation of this order is the belief that individuals are by nature free beings. Inseparable from this conviction is the idea of human beings as a subject who is by nature capable of doing both good and evil indiscriminately. According to John Paul II, these two truths are not only deeply rooted in the Christian vision of humanity but also allow for a proper understanding of the human situation in the world and point in the direction where attempts to build human communities should be directed.65 The point is that any social system that ignores these truths is doomed to failure. The disregard of human freedom and the disregard of man’s ability to do both good and evil, sooner or later, leads to the decomposition of a given order and destroys social peace. This decomposition and the destruction of peace are thus more or less a direct consequence of the attempt to build a social system whose ideological foundations are incompatible with the ontic condition of man.66

The above observations have, according to John Paul II, three extremely important consequences. The first is that the purpose of any criticism of malfunctioning democratic social orders (and not only theirs) should be not so much to point out some institutional solutions that should be introduced so that the given system begins to function better, but rather to find the erroneous ideological foundations behind certain solutions. Second, any attempt to repair a malfunctioning democracy should begin, first and foremost, by properly shaping the ethos of a given society. This can be achieved by helping parents to raise their children properly and by implementing certain socio-educational projects (e.g., in schools and foundations).67 Thirdly, the greater the influence of Christian revelation on the moral attitudes of society, the more properly the democratic order will function in it and the more it will serve the cause of peace.68

The last of these consequences is particularly interesting. In its light, the obligation that the Pope imposes on Christians today becomes extremely clear. According to the Pope, it is not the task of Christians to support specific institutional solutions in public life. However, given the deep connection between the Christian vision of reality and the moral ideas underlying democracy, it can be said, according to John Paul II, that the future of democracy and its further peaceful development depend directly on Christianity. The Pope emphasizes that, without the participation of Christians in the construction of the proper ethos of the societies in question, the continued existence of democratic regimes is in jeopardy. Thus, world peace is threatened. The passivity of Christians in this regard threatens the very destruction of democratic orders and consequently the proper protection of human freedom and social peace. The point is that no other religion (e.g., Islam, Hinduism, Buddhism, Judaism) has the ideological potential to serve the cause of democratizing societies and building world peace as well as Christianity.69

The fulfillment by Christians of this papal commitment seems necessary because of a rather paradoxical structural characteristic of the democratic order and its effects, which can already be observed quite well today. A democratic state cannot guarantee, in itself, the ethical foundation upon which it rests. Perhaps, expressing this differently for clarity’s sake, the democratic order can only exist because the freedom it guarantees to its citizens is largely regulated from within by the citizens themselves, guided by certain moral principles. At the same time, conversely, a democratic state cannot enforce compliance with certain moral rules and prohibitions by means of authoritarian coercion. Were the state to do so, it would be tantamount to making totalitarian claims that are completely contrary to the spirit of democracy. It is this paradoxical feature of the democratic order that is largely responsible for the gradual weakening of democratic societies. This is because democratic societies increasingly reject or deny the moral principles that form the ideological foundation of democracy. The process of this disappearance began around the time of the enlightenment. At that time, societies that were building democracy through the secularization of public life were cut off from the spiritual layers that animate the proper ethos of democracy and which the democratic state cannot (because it cannot) reproduce with the instruments at its disposal.70 Thus, with the passage of time, the link between the actual ethos of a given society and the Christian vision of reality gradually weakened. In turn, the fragility of this connection, as based on John Paul II’s reflections, means that the future of democracy and its peaceful development in a given society are at risk. Therefore, to re-establish this link, as it were, Christians should actively participate in shaping the ethos of the societies in which they currently live.71

The essence of the Pope’s idea of democratic public order outlined above is the assertion that this order, to function peacefully, requires an appropriate ethos that is close to Christian revelation and, in principle, one might even say grows out of it. Thus, the space of public life cannot be morally empty (as Popper desired), nor can it be filled with morally inadequate content (as Rousseau, among others, proposed). In both cases, the peaceful functioning of democracy in each society is threatened. Therefore, John Paul II obliges Christians to actively participate in the construction of an appropriate ethos in democratic societies. After all, Christianity seems to be uniquely predestined to create and constantly renew this ethos in given societies (something that de Tocqueville failed to observe).

Advertisement

6. Conclusion

The initial hypothesis advanced the observation that the authors of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, in its first article, expressed the conviction that freedom takes precedence over equality, and as the research revealed during the analysis, they were quite right. This means that a peacefully established public order should, first and foremost, protect the inherent freedom of all people and only secondarily ensure equality, regardless of how it is understood. Any attempt to reverse this order, as was the case, for example, with Rousseau’s project, in the near or distant future, threatens the loss of personal freedom for a significant part of the members of the order in question and endangers social peace. Therefore, we must agree with Popper, who claims that the basis of a peacefully organized society is respect for the freedom of all its members. Consequently, democracy should be considered as the general model of a peacefully organized public order today. However, the Austrian thinker erroneously postulated that this respect is tantamount to leaving the space of public life in a democracy morally empty. In a democratic order, in which citizens have no general moral guidelines on which to base their specific choices, certain processes occur that threaten the destruction of the system and the outbreak of social unrest. De Tocqueville, recognizing this danger, indicated that democracy needs the religious consciousness of its citizens to function peacefully. Thus, only in a religious society is it possible to maintain an appropriate ethos that guarantees the peaceful functioning and development of democracy. John Paul II, expanding upon the reflections of de Tocqueville, noted that the ethos of democracy not only coincides with the Christian vision of reality but also even grows directly out of it. On this basis, the Pope imposed certain obligations on modern Christians, pointing out that the future and further peaceful development of democracy directly depend on their fulfillment.

In the light of these considerations, it can be said that

  1. A condition for peace is that people respect each other’s freedom. This means that in order to guarantee peace, it is necessary to secure a “space” for people to exercise their own freedom sufficiently so as not to violate the freedom of others.

  2. The future of democracy, and therefore the effectiveness of the protection of human freedom and social peace, depends directly on the active presence of Christians in the public life of the communities concerned.

  3. Christians, through their educational and social activities which promote Christian values in particular societies, will contribute to the renewal of the ethos of faith in these societies which guarantees the peaceful functioning and development of democracy.

  4. Of course, it should not be forgotten that this is not the most important task that Christians have to carry out, nor should the danger of their peculiar appropriation of public life be underestimated. Nevertheless, in the light of the above analyses, any attempt to exclude the Christian vision of man from the moral space of modern democracy must be considered completely flawed as this threatens its complete destruction and destroys the chance of preserving peaceful relations between human beings.

References

  1. 1. Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Available from: https://www.un.org/en/about-us/universal-declaration-of-human-rights [Accessed: November 23, 2023]
  2. 2. Rousseau JJ. The Social Contract. Available from: https://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/economics/rousseau/social-contract/ch01.htm#002, Book1, Chapter 1: Subject of the first book [Accessed: November 23, 2023]
  3. 3. Starzewski M. Wstęp. In: Rousseau JJ, editor. O umowie społecznej, compiled and translated by M. Starzewski. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo De Agostini; 2002. pp. XIX-XXII
  4. 4. Rousseau JJ. On the Origin of the Inequality of Mankind. Available from: https://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/economics/rousseau/inequality/ch02.htm, The Second Part [Accessed: November 23, 2023]
  5. 5. Szahaj A, Jakubowski MN. Filozofia polityki. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN; 2005
  6. 6. Król M. Historia myśli politycznej od Machiavellego po czasy współczesne. Gdańsk: Wydawnictwo Arche; 2001
  7. 7. Rousseau JJ. The Social Contract, Book IV, Chapter 2: Voting. Available from: https://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/economics/rousseau/social-contract/ch04.htm#002 [Accessed: November 23, 2023]
  8. 8. Rousseau JJ. The Social Contract, Book 1, Chapter 6: The social compact. Available from: https://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/economics/rousseau/social-contract/ch01.htm#006 [Accessed: November 23, 2023]
  9. 9. Rousseau JJ. The Social Contract, Book 1, Chapter 9: Real Property. Available from: https://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/economics/rousseau/social-contract/ch01.htm#009 [Accessed: November 23, 2023]
  10. 10. Rousseau JJ. The Social Contract, Book 1, Chapter 8: The Civil State. Available from: https://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/economics/rousseau/social-contract/ch01.htm#008 [Accessed: November 23, 2023]
  11. 11. Hudzik JP. Wykłady z filozofii polityki. Lublin: Wydawnictwo UMCS; 2002
  12. 12. Copleston F. Historia filozofii. Od Wolffa do Kanta. Vol. 6, translated by J. Łoziński. Warszawa: Instytut Wydawniczy PAX; 2005
  13. 13. Nowakowski PT. Rousseau Jean-Jacques. In: Powszechna encyklopedia filozofii. Vol. 8. Lublin: Polskie Towarzystwo Tomasza z Akwinu; 2007. pp. 829-830
  14. 14. Drozdowicz Z. Filozofia Oświecenia. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN; 2006
  15. 15. Popper KR. Unended Quest: An Intellectual Autobiography. London: Fontana Books; 1976
  16. 16. Popper KR. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Routledge; 2000
  17. 17. Popper KR. The Open Society and its Enemies. Vol. 1-2. London: Routledge; 1947
  18. 18. MacIntyre A. Krótka historia etyki. Historia filozofii moralności od czasów Homera do XX wieku, translated and compiled by A. Chmielewski. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN; 1995
  19. 19. Szacki J. Spotkania z utopią. Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Sic!; 2000
  20. 20. Chmielewski A, editor. Przyszłość jest otwarta – rozmowa z Sir Karlem Popperem. In: Filozofia Poppera. Wrocław: Analiza krytyczna; 2003. pp. 234-246
  21. 21. Popper KR. The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul; 1957
  22. 22. Popper KR. Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul; 1963/1989
  23. 23. Chmielewski A. Społeczeństwo otwarte czy wspólnota? Filozoficzne i moralne podstawy nowoczesnego liberalizmu oraz jego krytyka we współczesnej filozofii społecznej. Wrocław: Wydawnictwo Arboretum; 2001
  24. 24. Tocqueville de A. Democracy in America. Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University; 2002
  25. 25. Kłoczowski P. O demokratycznych skłonnościach i republikańskich hamulcach. In: Legutko R, Kloczkowski J, editors. Oblicza demokracji. Kraków: Ośrodek Myśli Politycznej; 2002. pp. 253-257
  26. 26. Salij J. Teokratyczne roszczenia współczesnej demokracji. Ethos. 1993;21-22:107-121
  27. 27. Schipperges KJ. Społeczeństwo egalitarne i związane z nim zagrożenia. In: Naród, Wolność, Liberalizm (Collective Ed.). Poznań: Wydawnictwo Pallottinum; 1994. pp. 257-276
  28. 28. Schooyans M. Totalitarne zagrożenie demokracji. Ethos. 1993;21-22:123-130
  29. 29. Novak M. Liberalizm – sprzymierzeniec czy wróg Kościoła. Poznań: W drodze; 1993
  30. 30. Zięba M. Kościół wobec liberalnej demokracji, In M. Novak, A. Rauscher, M. Zięba, Chrześcijaństwo, demokracja, kapitalizm, Poznań: W drodze; 1993. pp. 115-116
  31. 31. Böckenförde E. Wolność, państwo, Kościół. Kraków: Wydawnictwo Znak; 1994
  32. 32. Dahl R. O demokracji. Kraków: Wydawnictwo Znak; 2000
  33. 33. Stawrowski Z. Moralność a demokracja. In: Legutko R, Kloczkowski J, editors. Oblicza demokracji. Kraków: Ośrodek Myśli Politycznej; 2002. pp. 163-178
  34. 34. Novak M. Catholic Social Thought and Liberal Institutions: Freedom with Justice. Oxford: Transaction Publishers; 1984
  35. 35. John Paul II. Laborem Exercens. Vatican: Libreria Editrice Vaticana; 1981
  36. 36. Hayek, von FA. The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press; 1978
  37. 37. Strzelecki J. Wokół “Laborem exercens”. Ethos. 1990;11-12:291-306
  38. 38. John Paul II. Centesimus annus. Vatican: Libreria Editrice Vaticana; 1991
  39. 39. Krucina J. Od optymizmu “Populorum progressio” do troski “Sollicitudo rei socialis”. Ethos. 1990;11-12:307-317
  40. 40. John Paul II. Sollicitudo rei socialis. Vatican: Libreria Editrice Vaticana; 1987
  41. 41. Buttiglione R. Ku prawdziwej demokracji. Osoba, społeczeństwo i państwo w “Centesimus annus”. In Ethos. 1993;21-22:93-105
  42. 42. Życiński J. Ziarno samotności. Kraków: Wydawnictwo Znak; 1997
  43. 43. Novak M. The Spirit of Democratic Capitalism. New York: Rowman & Littlefield; 1991

Notes

  • See Ref. [1].
  • See Ref. [2].
  • See Ref. [3].
  • For example, in On the Origin of the Inequality of Mankind, J.J. Rousseau states: “The first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, bethought himself of saying This is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him, was the real founder of civil society. From how many crimes, wars and murders, from how many horrors and misfortunes might not any one have saved mankind, by pulling up the stakes, or filling up the ditch, and crying to his fellows, Beware of listening to this impostor; you are undone if you once forget that the fruits of the earth belong to us all, and the earth itself to nobody.” See Ref. [4].
  • See Ref. [5], p. 53.
  • See Ref. [6], p. 52–53.
  • “The more concert reigns in the assemblies, that is, the nearer opinion approaches unanimity, the greater is the dominance of the general will. On the other hand, long debates, dissensions and tumult proclaim the ascendancy of particular interests and the decline of the State.” See Ref. [7].
  • “If then we discard from the social compact what is not of its essence, we shall find that it reduces itself to the following terms: Each of us puts his person and all his power in common under the supreme direction of the general will, and, in our corporate capacity, we receive each member as an indivisible part of the whole. At once, in place of the individual personality of each contracting party, this act of association creates a moral and collective body, composed of as many members as the assembly contains votes, and receiving from this act its unity, its common identity, its life and its will. This public person, so formed by the union of all other persons formerly took the name of city, and now takes that of Republic or body politic; it is called by its members State when passive. Sovereign when active, and Power when compared with others like itself. Those who are associated in it take collectively the name of people, and severally are called citizens, as sharing in the sovereign power, and subjects, as being under the laws of the State.” See Ref. [8].
  • “(…) instead of destroying natural inequality, the fundamental compact substitutes, for such physical inequality as nature may have set up between men, an equality that is moral and legitimate, and that men, who may be unequal in strength or intelligence, become everyone equal by convention and legal right.” See Ref. [9].
  • “What man loses by the social contract is his natural liberty and an unlimited right to everything he tries to get and succeeds in getting; what he gains is civil liberty and the proprietorship of all he possesses. If we are to avoid mistake in weighing one against the other, we must clearly distinguish natural liberty, which is bounded only by the strength of the individual, from civil liberty, which is limited by the general will; and possession, which is merely the effect of force or the right of the first occupier, from property, which can be founded only on a positive title. We might, over and above all this, add, to what man acquires in the civil state, moral liberty, which alone makes him truly master of himself; for the mere impulse of appetite is slavery, while obedience to a law which we prescribe to ourselves is liberty.” See Ref. [10].
  • See A. Szahaj, M.N. Jakubowski, Filozofia, p. 54–55.
  • “In order then that the social compact may not be an empty formula, it tacitly includes the undertaking, which alone can give force to the rest, that whoever refuses to obey the general will shall be compelled to do so by the whole body. This means nothing less than that he will be forced to be free; for this is the condition which, by giving each citizen to his country, secures him against all personal dependence. In this lies the key to the working of the political machine; this alone legitimizes civil undertakings, which, without it, would be absurd, tyrannical, and liable to the most frightful abuses.” See Ref. [10].
  • See M. Król, Historia, p. 54–56.
  • See Ref. [11], p. 42–44.
  • See, e.g. Ref. [12], p.88–92; Ref. [13]. It should not be forgotten, of course, that J.J. Rousseau is also the author of a number of extremely valuable philosophical ideas that provided important inspiration for later philosophers. For a brief presentation of such ideas, see Ref. [14], p. 148.
  • See Ref. [15], p. 36.
  • See M. Król, Historia, p. 172.
  • See J.P. Hudzik, Wykłady, p. 142–145. It is worth noting that the project of a proper social order and its development, formulated in this way, is deeply connected with the so-called concept of falsificationism, developed by Karl Raimund Popper within the framework of his research on science. For example, the Austrian thinker writes the following about the nature of scientific progress: “Bold ideas, unjustified anticipations, and speculative thought, are our only means for interpreting nature: our only organon, our only instrument, for grasping her.” See Ref. [16], p. 280.
  • “In what follows, the magical or tribal or collectivist society will also be called the closed society, and the society in which individuals are confronted with personal decisions, the open society. The closed society at its best can be justly compared to an organism. The so-called organic or biological theory of the state is to a certain extent applicable here, since the closed society lacks those features of the open society which must defeat every attempt to apply this theory. The features I have in mind are those connected with the fact that, in the open society, many members strive to take the place of other members. This may express itself, for instance, in such an important phenomenon as class struggle. We cannot find anything like class struggle in an organism. The cells or tissues of an organism which are sometimes said to correspond to the members of a state, may perhaps compete for food; but there is no inherent tendency on the part of the legs to become the brain, or of other members of the body to become the belly. Since there is nothing in the organism to correspond to one of the most important features of the open society, competition for status among its members, the so-called organic theory of the state is based on a false analogy. The closed society, on the other hand, does not know much of such tendencies. Its institutions, including its castes, are sacrosanct – taboo.” See Ref. [17], p. 152–153.
  • See A. Szahaj, M.N. Jakubowski, Filozofia, p. 111.
  • This does not mean, however, that Karl Raimund Popper does not include the French philosopher in a very broad current that creates various types of models of the “closed society.” He writes, for example: “(…) the collectivist Hegel, like Plato, visualizes the state as an organism; and following Rousseau who had furnished it with a collective ‘general’ will, Hegel furnishes it with a conscious and thinking essence, its ‘reason’ or ‘Spirit’. This Spirit, whose ‘very essence is activity’ (which shows its dependence on Rousseau), is at the same time the collective Spirit of the Nation that forms the state.” See Ref. [17], p. 35.
  • See Ref. [18], p. 238–244.
  • See Ref. [19], p. 127.
  • “It is widely believed that a truly scientific and philosophical attitude toward politics, and a deeper understanding of social life in general, must be based upon a contemplation and interpretation of human history. While the ordinary man takes the setting of his life and the importance of hi$ personal experiences and struggles for granted, it is said that the social scientist or philosopher has to survey things from a higher plane. He sees the individual as a pawn, as a rather insignificant instrument in the general development of mankind. And the really important actors on the Stage of History he may find, perhaps, in the Great Nations and their Great Leaders, or perhaps in the Great Classes, or in the Great Ideas. However, this may be, he will try to understand the meaning of the play which is performed on that Stage; he will try to understand the laws of historical development. If he succeeds in this, he will, of course, be able to predict future developments. He might then put politics upon a solid basis and give us practical advice by telling us which political actions are likely to succeed or likely to fail.” See Ref. [17], p. 5–6.
  • This belief is called “historicism” by Karl Raimund Popper.
  • See Ref. [20]. Karl Raimund Popper devoted his entire book Die Zukunft ist offen (1985; written together with K. Lorenz) to the idea of the openness of history. One should also not forget the work The Open Universe: An Argument for Indeterminism (1982). This idea also appears there.
  • See Ref. [21], p. 39; Ref. [22], p. 339.
  • “In all matters, we can only learn by trial and error, by making mistakes and improvements; we can never rely on inspiration, although inspirations may be most valuable as long as they can be checked by experience. Accordingly, it is not reasonable to assume that a complete reconstruction of our social world would lead at once to a workable system. Rather we should expect that, owing to lack of experience, many mistakes would be made, which could be only eliminated by a long and laborious process of improvement; in other words, by that rational method of piecemeal engineering whose application we advocate. But those who dislike this method as insufficiently radical would have again to wipe out their freshly constructed society, in order to start anew with a clean canvas; and since the new start, for the same reasons, would not lead to perfection either, they would have to repeat this process without ever reaching anything. Those who admit this and are prepared to adopt our more modest method of piecemeal improvements, but only after the first canvas cleaning, can hardly escape the criticism that their first sweeping and violent measures were quite unnecessary. This irrational attitude which springs from an intoxication with dreams of a beautiful world is what I call Romanticism. It may seek its heavenly city in the past or in the future; it may preach ‘back to nature’ or ‘forward to a world of love and beauty’; but its appeal is always to our emotions rather than to reason. Even with the best intentions of realizing heaven on earth it only succeeds in realizing hell – that hell which man alone prepares for his fellows.” See Ref. [17], p. 147–148.
  • According to Karl Raimund Popper, the most important institutional advantage of the “open society” over the “closed society” seems to be that it allows reforms to be carried out peacefully, without violence. For the Austrian thinker, parliamentary democracy is the institutional embodiment of the “open society.” See e.g. Ref. [17], p. 140.
  • “Not only does the construction of institutions involve important moral decisions, but the functioning of even the best institutions will always depend, to a considerable degree, on its personnel. Institutions are like fortresses. They must be well designed and manned. This is often misunderstood by the critics of democracy. Democracy provides the institutional framework for the reform of political institutions (other than this framework). It makes possible the reform of institutions without using violence, and thereby the use of reason in the designing of new institutions and the adjusting of old ones. It cannot provide reason. The question of the intellectual and moral standard of its citizens is to a large degree a personal problem. (The idea that this problem can be tackled, in turn, by an institutional eugenic and educational control is, I believe, mistaken; some reasons for my belief will be given below.) It is quite wrong to blame democracy for the political shortcomings of a democratic state. We should rather blame ourselves. In a non-democratic state, the only way to achieve reasonable reforms is by the violent overthrow of the government, and the introduction of a democratic framework. Those who criticize democracy on any ‘moral’ grounds fail to distinguish between personal and institutional problems. It rests with us to improve matters. The democratic institutions cannot improve themselves. The problem of improving them is always a problem of persons rather than of institutions.” See Ref. [17], p. 110–111.
  • See Ref. [17], p. 99.
  • The point is that in the face of serious moral and political conflicts, liberalism cannot help but take sides, giving the lie to its official neutrality. See, e.g. Ref. [23], p. 176.
  • Because traditional moral values are at stake, A. de Tocqueville is often described as a conservative liberal. See, e.g. M. Król, Historia, p. 141–143; A. Szahaj, M.N. Jakubowski, Filozofia, p. 68.
  • “It is evident to all alike that a great democratic revolution is going on among us; but there are two opinions as to its nature and consequences. To some it appears to be a novel accident, which as such may still be checked; to others it seems irresistible, because it is the most uniform, the most ancient, and the most permanent tendency which is to be found in history. (…) Whithersoever we turn our eyes we shall witness the same continual revolution throughout the whole of Christendom. The various occurrences of national existence have everywhere turned to the advantage of democracy. (…) Will it stop now that it has grown so strong and its adversaries so weak? None can say which way we are going, for all terms of comparison are wanting. (…) It is not necessary that God himself should speak in order to disclose to us the unquestionable signs of His will; we can discern them in the habitual course of nature, and in the invariable tendency of events: I know, without a special revelation, that the planets move in the orbits traced by the Creator’s finger.” See Ref. [24], p. 13, 15–16.
  • See M. Król, Historia, p. 136. A. de Tocqueville described the workings of American democracy with the words: “In some countries a power exists which, though it is in a degree foreign to the social body, directs it, and forces it to pursue a certain track. In others the ruling force is divided, being partly within and partly without the ranks of the people. But nothing of the kind is to be seen in the United States; there society governs itself for itself. All power centres in its bosom; and scarcely an individual is to be meet with who would venture to conceive, or, still less, to express, the idea of seeking it elsewhere. The nation participates in the making of its laws by the choice of its legislators, and in the execution of them by the choice of the agents of the executive government; it may almost be said to govern itself, so feeble and so restricted is the share left to the administration, so little do the authorities forget their popular origin and the power from which they emanate.” See Ref. [24], p. 75.
  • “The heads of the State have never had any forethought for its exigencies, and its victories have been obtained without their consent or without their knowledge. The most powerful, the most intelligent, and the most moral classes of the nation have never attempted to connect themselves with it in order to guide it. The people has consequently been abandoned to its wild propensities, and it has grown up like those outcasts who receive their education in the public streets, and who are unacquainted with aught but the vices and wretchedness of society. The existence of a democracy was seemingly unknown, when on a sudden it took possession of the supreme power. Everything was then submitted to its caprices; it was worshipped as the idol of strength; until, when it was enfeebled by its own excesses, the legislator conceived the rash project of annihilating its power, instead of instructing it and correcting its vices; no attempt was made to fit it to govern, but all were bent on excluding it from the government.” See Ref. [24], p. 17.
  • “I think that democratic communities have a natural taste for freedom: left to themselves, they will seek it, cherish it, and view any privation of it with regret. But for equality, their passion is ardent, insatiable, incessant, invincible: they call for equality in freedom; and if they cannot obtain that, they still call for equality in slavery. They will endure poverty, servitude, barbarism – but they will not endure aristocracy.” See Ref. [24], p. 573.
  • See Ref. [24], p. 573–575.
  • See Ref. [24], p. 576–580.
  • See Ref. [24], p. 599–603.
  • See Ref. [24], p. 493–497.
  • Very interestingly this observation of the French thinker is described by a contemporary Polish researcher M. Król. He notes that some of the remarks, Tocqueville devotes to democracy seem to anticipate a certain way of thinking about society and democratic institutions that is characteristic of later times. Democracy will be seen as a system for the triumph of mediocrity, the decline of the arts and sciences, and, more generally, the degradation of human nature. The merits of democracy will be at least debatable for many thinkers, while the damage it has done will be undeniable. However, unlike the catastrophic, aristocratic, nihilistic, or extreme conservative critics of democracy, Tocqueville, while recognizing the evils that democracy can produce, does not stop there, but considers how to remedy them in the most permanent (structural - as we would say today) way possible. In other words, Tocqueville is looking for ways to ensure that democracy does not take on a revolutionary character and destroy the values that make human life meaningful. See M. Król, Historia, p. 135–136.
  • See M. Król, Historia, p. 136–143.
  • It is worth noting here that, according to A. de Tocqueville, ideas of a religious nature have a more or less direct influence on all human activity: “There is hardly any human action, however particular a character be assigned to it, which does not originate in some very general idea men have conceived of the Deity, of his relation to mankind, of the nature of their own souls, and of their duties to their fellow-creatures. Nor can anything prevent these ideas from being the common spring from which everything else emanates.” See Ref. [24], p. 503.
  • “Men are therefore immeasurably interested in acquiring fixed ideas of God, of the soul, and of their common duties to their Creator and their fellow-men; for doubt on these first principles would abandon all their actions to the impulse of chance, and would condemn them to live, to a certain extent, powerless and undisciplined. (…) The first object and one of the principal advantages of religions is to furnish to each of these fundamental questions a solution which is at once clear, precise, intelligible to the mass of mankind, and lasting. There are religions which are very false and very absurd; but it may be affirmed that any religion which remains within the circle I have just traced, without aspiring to go beyond it (as many religions have attempted to do, for the purpose of enclosing on every side the free progress of the human mind), imposes a salutary restraint on the intellect; and it must be admitted that, if it do not save men in another world, such religion is at least very conducive to their happiness and their greatness in this. This is more especially true of men living in free countries. When the religion of a people is destroyed, doubt gets hold of the highest portions of the intellect, and half paralyzes all the rest of its powers. (…) Such a condition cannot but enervate the soul, relax the springs of the will, and prepare a people for servitude. Nor does it only happen, in such a case, that they allow their freedom to be wrested from them; they frequently themselves surrender it. (…) The greatest advantage of religion is to inspire diametrically contrary principles. There is no religion which does not place the object of man’s desires above and beyond the treasures of earth, and which does not naturally raise his soul to regions far above those of the senses. Nor is there any which does not impose on man some sort of duties to his kind, and thus draws him at times from the contemplation of himself. This occurs in religions the most false and dangerous. (…) The chief concern of religions is to purify, to regulate, and to restrain the excessive and exclusive taste for well-being which men feel at periods of equality; but they would err in attempting to control it completely or to eradicate it. They will not succeed in curing men of the love of riches: but they may still persuade men to enrich themselves by none but honest means. (…) Thus it is that, by respecting all democratic tendencies not absolutely contrary to herself, and by making use of several of them for her own purposes, religion sustains an advantageous struggle with that spirit of individual independence which is her most dangerous antagonist.” See Ref. [24], p. 503–506, 510–511.
  • See, e.g.: Refs. [11, 25, 26, 27, 28].
  • See, e.g.: Ref. [29], p. 296–305; Ref. [30]; Ref. [31], p. 166–197; Ref. [32], p. 145–147; Ref. [33].
  • Of course, it must be remembered that the Catholic Church, in its official social doctrine, never proposes specific institutional solutions to be applied in public life. This constructive criticism of democracy by John Paul II therefore means that democracy appears to him as the public order that most fully realizes the Catholic vision of social reality in the present social situation. Michael Novak, a contemporary American thinker, encourages the reader to read the Pope’s reflection: “(…) Catholic social thought has slowly but steadily come to embrace the basic institutions of the liberal society, in the economic, the political, and the moral-cultural systems. It is time for that process to become more self- conscious, self-confident, and boldly imaginative. I do not believe that “Catholic social thought should serve the liberal society. On the contrary, I hold that the liberal society, among known and workable present and future societies, best serves Catholic social thought: best uplifts the poor, institutionalizes the dignity of the human person, makes possible the growth and manifold activities of human associations of every sort, and conspires to establish a more voluntary and open and communitarian form of life than any society of the past, present, or foreseeable future.” See Ref. [34], p. 38.
  • In Laborem Exercens, John Paul II states: “While in the present document we return to this question once more-without however any intention of touching on all the topics that concern it-this is not merely in order to gather together and repeat what is already contained in the Church’s teaching. It is rather in order to highlight-perhaps more than has been done before-the fact that human work is a key, probably the essential key, to the whole social question, if we try to see that question really from the point of view of man’s good. And if the solution-or rather the gradual solution-of the social question, which keeps coming up and becomes ever more complex, must be sought in the direction of > > making life more human<<, then the key, namely human work, acquires fundamental and decisive importance.” See Ref [35], No. 3.
  • See Ref. [35], No. 4.
  • See Ref. [35], No. 9.
  • See Ref. [35], No. 7.
  • In Laborem exercens, John Paul II calls this criterion the “personalist argument” (No. 15).
  • In Laborem Exercens (No. 11–15), the Pope, referring to the communist system that existed in many Eastern European countries at that time, points out that it is a perfect example of an inappropriate organization of society, since in it social life (and especially the economic sphere) is strictly controlled by a certain narrowly limited group of people. This means that, in societies of the communist type, the individual person is objectified, and his freedom is constantly threatened. John Paul II points out that even in so-called “primitive capitalism” human dignity is violated and freedom is destroyed, because in it the concrete human being is treated as a tool for the production of certain goods and is placed on an equal footing with the entire set of material means of production. Nevertheless, according to the Pope, the communist system is more harmful when it comes to violating human freedom. A good illustration of the Pope’s assessment of the harmfulness of the communist system is the observation of F.A. von Hayek, one of the most important representatives of the so-called Austrian School of Economics: “A complete monopoly of employment, such as would exist in a fully socialist state in which the government was the only employer and the owner of all the instruments of production, would possess unlimited powers of coercion. As Leon Trotsky discovered: In a country where the sole employer is the State, opposition means death by slow starvation. The old principle, who does not work shall not eat, has been replaced by a new one: who does not obey shall not eat.” See Ref. [36], p. 137.
  • See Ref. [34], p. 238.
  • See Ref. [37], p. 303.
  • John Paul II lists these and similar moral obligations and discusses, among other things, the moral basis for a peaceful economic life. See Ref. [38], No. 32.
  • In the light of the encyclical Sollicitudo rei socialis, it can be said that the obstacles to the peaceful development of human societies are primarily of a moral nature. The Pope attaches much less importance to various difficulties of an economic and political nature. See Ref. [39], p. 315.
  • The point is that the democratic functioning of the social order as such creates a climate conducive to the spread of wrong attitudes. To use the Pope’s language, one would have to say that democracy as such (not only, of course, and not even primarily) favors the perpetuation in society of the so-called structures of sin from which the “two are very typical: on the one hand, the all-consuming desire for profit, and on the other, the thirst for power, with the intention of imposing one’s will upon others.” See Ref. [40], No. 37.
  • John Paul II, in Sollicitudo rei socialis, mentions the dangers of excessive material development in addition to the drama of underdevelopment (especially economic) of many human societies. Particularly noteworthy, according to the Pope, is the peculiar spiritual underdevelopment of many societies that accompanies their excessive economic development. In the aforementioned encyclical, the Pope states: “A disconcerting conclusion about the most recent period should serve to enlighten us: side-by-side with the miseries of underdevelopment, themselves unacceptable, we find ourselves up against a form of super-development, equally inadmissible. Because like the former it is contrary to what is good and to true happiness. This super-development, which consists in an excessive availability of every kind of material goods for the benefit of certain social groups, easily makes people slaves of possession and of immediate gratification, with no other horizon than the multiplication or continual replacement of the things already owned with others still better. This is the so-called civilization of consumption or consumerism, which involves so much throwing-away and waste. An object already owned but now superseded by something better is discarded, with no thought of its possible lasting value, nor of some other human being who is poorer. All of us experience firsthand the sad effects of this blind submission to pure consumerism: in the first place a crass materialism, and at the same time a radical dissatisfaction, because one quickly learns - unless one is shielded from the flood of publicity and the ceaseless and tempting offers of products - that the more one possesses the more one wants, while deeper aspirations remain unsatisfied and perhaps even stifled. (…) The evil does not consist in having as such, but in possessing without regard for the quality and the ordered hierarchy of the goods one has. Quality and hierarchy arise from the subordination of goods and their availability to man’s being and his true vocation.” See Ref. [40], No. 28.
  • “The intrinsic connection between authentic development and respect for human rights once again reveals the moral character of development: the true elevation of man, in conformity with the natural and historical vocation of each individual, is not attained only by exploiting the abundance of goods and services, or by having available perfect infrastructures. When individuals and communities do not see a rigorous respect for the moral, cultural and spiritual requirements, based on the dignity of the person and on the proper identity of each community, beginning with the family and religious societies, then all the rest - availability of goods, abundance of technical resources applied to daily life, a certain level of material well-being - will prove unsatisfying and in the end contemptible.” See Ref. [40], No. 33.
  • “Solidarity helps us to see the other-whether a person, people or nation-not just as some kind of instrument, with a work capacity and physical strength to be exploited at low cost and then discarded when no longer useful, but as our neighbor, a helper (cf. Gen 2:18–20), to be made a sharer, on a par with ourselves, in the banquet of life to which all are equally invited by God. Hence the importance of reawakening the religious awareness of individuals and peoples. (…) Development that does not include the cultural, transcendent, and religious dimensions of man and society, to the extent that it does not recognize the existence of such dimensions and does not endeavor to direct its goals and priorities toward the same, is even less conducive to authentic liberation.” See Ref. [40], No. 39, 46.
  • In Sollicitudo rei socialis, the Pope makes clear the unique responsibility of Christians for the peaceful development and functioning of human communities: “I wish to appeal with simplicity and humility to everyone, to all men and women without exception. I wish to ask them to be convinced of the seriousness of the present moment and of each one’s individual responsibility, and to implement - by the way they live as individuals and as families, by the use of their resources, by their civic activity, by contributing to economic and political decisions and by personal commitment to national and international undertakings - the measures inspired by solidarity and love of preference for the poor. This is what is demanded by the present moment and above all by the very dignity of the human person, the indestructible image of God the Creator, which is identical in each one of us. In this commitment, the sons and daughters of the Church must serve as examples and guides, for they are called upon, in conformity with the program announced by Jesus himself in the synagogue at Nazareth, to preach good news to the poor…to proclaim release to the captives and recovering of sight to the blind, to set at liberty those who are oppressed, to proclaim the accept able year of the Lord (Lk 4:18–19). It is appropriate to emphasize the preeminent role that belongs to the laity (…). It is their task to animate temporal realities with Christian commitment, by which they show that they are witnesses and agents of peace and justice. I wish to address especially those who, through the sacrament of Baptism and the profession of the same Creed, share a real, though imperfect, communion with us.” See Ref. [40], No. 47.
  • See Ref. [34], p. 236–254.
  • See Ref. [41].
  • “Nevertheless, it cannot be forgotten that the manner in which the individual exercises his freedom is conditioned in innumerable ways. While these certainly have an influence on freedom, they do not determine it; they make the exercise of freedom more difficult or less difficult, but they cannot destroy it. Not only is it wrong from the ethical point of view to disregard human nature, which is made for freedom, but in practice it is impossible to do so. Where society is so organized as to reduce arbitrarily or even suppress the sphere in which freedom is legitimately exercised, the result is that the life of society becomes progressively disorganized and goes into decline. Moreover, man, who was created for freedom, bears within himself the wound of original sin, which constantly draws him toward evil and puts him in need of redemption. Not only is this doctrine an integral part of Christian revelation; it also has great hermeneutical value insofar as it helps one to understand human reality. Man tends toward good, but he is also capable of evil. (…) The social order will be all the more stable, the more it takes this fact (…).” See Ref. [38], No. 25.
  • John Paul II, in Centesimus Annus, referring to the general crisis of the family in the modern world and the spread of consumerist attitudes, especially in capitalist countries, says: “These criticisms are directed not so much against an economic system as against an ethical and cultural system. The economy in fact is only one aspect and one dimension of the whole of human activity. If economic life is absolutized, if the production and consumption of goods become the centre of social life and society’s only value, not subject to any other value, the reason is to be found not so much in the economic system itself as in the fact that the entire socio-cultural system, by ignoring the ethical and religious dimension, has been weakened, and ends by limiting itself to the production of goods and services alone.” See Ref. [38], No. 39.
  • “Authentic democracy is possible only (…) based on a correct conception of the human person. It requires that the necessary conditions be present for the advancement both of the individual through education and formation in true ideals, and of the subjectivity of society through the creation of structures of participation and shared responsibility. Nowadays there is a tendency to claim that agnosticism and skeptical relativism are the philosophy and the basic attitude which correspond to democratic forms of political life. Those who are convinced that they know the truth and firmly adhere to it are considered unreliable from a democratic point of view, since they do not accept that truth is determined by the majority, or that it is subject to variation according to different political trends. It must be observed in this regard that if there is no ultimate truth to guide and direct political activity, then ideas and convictions can easily be manipulated for reasons of power. As history demonstrates, a democracy without values easily turns into open or thinly disguised totalitarianism. Nor does the Church close her eyes to the danger of fanaticism or fundamentalism among those who, in the name of an ideology which purports to be scientific or religious, claim the right to impose on others their own concept of what is true and good. Christian truth is not of this kind. (…) Furthermore, in constantly reaffirming the transcendent dignity of the person, the Church’s method is always that of respect for freedom. (…) The Christian upholds freedom and serves it, constantly offering to others the truth which he has known (cf. Jn 8:31–32), in accordance with the missionary nature of his vocation. While paying heed to every fragment of truth which he encounters in the life experience and in the culture of individuals and of nations, he will not fail to affirm in dialog with others all that his faith and the correct use of reason have enabled him to understand.” See Ref. [38], No. 46.
  • J. Życiński, a contemporary commentator on the thought of John Paul II, notes that from the perspective of the positive assessment of liberalism presented in Centesimus Annus, one should not expect the Church to extol the charms of this system. While accepting the general principle of the inviolability of human freedom, the Church cannot avoid specific questions about the inevitable limitations of values that occur at the level of the economy, culture, and ethics. See Ref. [42], p. 67.
  • See E. Böckenförde, Wolność, p. 99–121.
  • The question of the relationship between Christian revelation and the moral foundation of democracy is analyzed by M. Novak in a very interesting and original way. It seems that his thoughts have had an enormous influence on the thought of John Paul II. In fact, there is a striking similarity between the two concepts, and the American thinker’s reflections precede those of the Pope in time. This similarity is not accidental. As is well known, M. Novak was a papal advisor at the time when John Paul II wrote the encyclical Centesimus annus. In the context of the relationship between the Christian understanding of reality and the moral foundations of democracy, and in view of the declining influence of Christianity on the actual ethos of democratic societies, the following statement by the American author is very interesting: “(…) the moral-cultural system is the chief dynamic force behind the rise both of a democratic political system and of a liberal economic system. The moral-cultural system is the sine qua non of the political system and economic system. Neglect of it bodes ill. One result of this curious neglect of the moral-cultural resources of our own system is the abandonment of the exposition of these systems to social scientists and technicians. Yet such experts are barred by their disciplines from the very sorts of moral inquiry most required. The second result is that this system makes no moral presentation of itself to the word. It discusses itself, and allows itself to be discusses, in sheerly material and procedural terms. (…) A third result is that morale is lowered in the West. Human beings do not live by bread alone. They must believe their political and economic activities have moral significance. Their stamina, their perseverance in difficulties, their sense of well-being and purpose-all these depend on the strength of the moral-cultural system in which they participate. (…) Democratic capitalism is more likely to perish through its loss of its indispensable ideas and morals than trough weaknesses in its political system and economic system. In its moral-cultural system lies its weakest link.” See Ref. [43], p. 185–186.

Written By

Zdzisław Kieliszek

Submitted: 11 December 2023 Reviewed: 13 December 2023 Published: 22 March 2024